Deterministic Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics
The dominance of the Copenhagen interpretation is the result of a historical accident (Cushing, 1994). At the Solvay conference in 1927, Louis de Broglie put forward the deterministic pilot wave theory, described later. Never slow to criticize, Pauli jumped up and demolished de Broglie’s proposal, a...
Saved in:
Published in | Theology and Modern Physics pp. 159 - 186 |
---|---|
Main Author | |
Format | Book Chapter |
Language | English |
Published |
Routledge
2005
|
Subjects | |
Online Access | Get full text |
Cover
Loading…
Summary: | The dominance of the Copenhagen interpretation is the result of a historical
accident (Cushing, 1994). At the Solvay conference in 1927, Louis de Broglie
put forward the deterministic pilot wave theory, described later. Never slow to
criticize, Pauli jumped up and demolished de Broglie’s proposal, and de Broglie
was so discouraged by this that he did not develop his interpretation any
further. The Copenhagen interpretation was then developed by Bohr,
Heisenberg, Pauli and many others, as described in the previous chapter. It
was strongly supported by von Neumann’s proof of the impossibility of hidden
variables. Years later, in 1952, Bohm published a deterministic hidden variable
theory, showing that there must be something wrong with von Neumann’s
proof. The error was found by John Bell in 1966, as described in the last
chapter, and he also showed how Pauli’s objections to de Broglie’s original idea
can be answered. If this had been done at the conference in 1927, quantum
mechanics could have been interpreted deterministically from the beginning.
The essential mistake in the Copenhagen interpretation is to treat it as acomplete account of the behaviour of each individual system. It is frequently
claimed that it enables us to calculate, at least in principle, everything that can
be measured. Thus Hooft (1997, p. 11) said that ‘The laws of quantum mechanics have been formulated very accurately. We know exactly how to compute
anything we would like to know.’ Also Peierls (1997, p. 25) has said that
quantum mechanics ‘had become a complete and consistent scheme capable of
giving a unique answer to any questions relating to actual or possible
observations’. Even if this were true, it would not imply that it is the final
complete theory, for it is always possible that some new phenomenon might be
found that cannot be calculated quantum-mechanically. However, it is not
true: there are many phenomena such as the time of decay of a radioactive
nucleus, or the direction a particle is scattered by a nucleus, that cannot be
calculated, even in principle. Quantum mechanics is therefore an incomplete
theory. We can only calculate the statistical properties of these systems, such as
the half-life of a radioactive decay or the differential scattering cross-section
that gives the probabilities that a particle is scattered through various angles.
All measurements of quantum systems are of this statistical character. It might
be thought that the possibility of making measurements on a single electron
provides an exception to this. However, even in such cases the electron is
continually bathed in a fluctuating background radiation from nearby atoms.
Since this is variable, that electron is a member of an ensemble of electrons
subject to different fluctuations. All these examples clearly demonstrate thestatistical character of quantum mechanics. ‘I am rather firmly convinced’,
Einstein (in Schilpp, 1949, pp. 666, 671) remarked, ‘that the essentially statistical
character of contemporary quantum theory is solely to be ascribed to fact that
this theory operates with an incomplete description of physical systems’. As a
result, ‘the c-function is to be understood as the description not of a single
system but of an ensemble of systems’. So, ‘if the statistical quantum theory
does not pretend to describe the individual system completely, it appears
unavoidable to look elsewhere for a complete description of the individual
systems’. Thus ‘the difficulties of theoretical interpretation disappear, if one
views the quantum-mechanical description as a description of an ensemble of
systems’. If this is achieved, ‘the statistical theory would, within the framework
of future physics, take an approximately analogous position to statistical
mechanics within the framework of classical mechanics’. ‘Thus, essentially,
nothing has changed since Galileo or Newton or Faraday concerning the status
of the ‘‘observer’’ or our ‘‘consciousness’’ or of our ‘‘information’’ in physics’
(Popper, 1982, p. 46). Once this is accepted, the quantum paradoxes that
plagued the Copenhagen interpretation are easily resolved, as described below.
In any textbook of quantum mechanics problems such as the calculation ofthe energy levels of the hydrogen atom are solved as if that hydrogen atom is
alone in the universe. As Feynman (1972) remarked, ‘when we solve a
quantum-mechanical problem, what we really do is to divide the universe into
two parts – the system in which we are interested and the rest of the universe.
We then usually act as if the system in which we are interested comprised the
whole universe.’ In fact, however, every hydrogen atom on which measurements are made is surrounded by other atoms and exposed to their radiations.
Quantum mechanics somehow takes this into account and gives the average
behaviour of an ensemble of hydrogen atoms. A more detailed theory takes
these influences into account. One attempt to do this is stochastic
electrodynamics, described in a later section. |
---|---|
ISBN: | 9780754636229 0754636232 0754636224 9780754636236 |
DOI: | 10.4324/9781315236407-13 |