Introduction: New genetic identities?

Recent innovations in biomedical knowledge – notably in the field of genetics and genomics – have created extraordinarily diverse possibilities in the natural and clinical sciences. At the same time, they have opened up an equally varied range of opportunities and challenges for social and cultural a...

Full description

Saved in:
Bibliographic Details
Published inNew Genetics, New Identities pp. 13 - 22
Format Book Chapter
LanguageEnglish
Published Routledge
Subjects
Online AccessGet full text
DOI10.4324/9780203962923-8

Cover

Loading…
More Information
Summary:Recent innovations in biomedical knowledge – notably in the field of genetics and genomics – have created extraordinarily diverse possibilities in the natural and clinical sciences. At the same time, they have opened up an equally varied range of opportunities and challenges for social and cultural analysts. The translation of social relations and categories into biological terms, and the simultaneous expansion of biomedical engagement with more and more aspects of everyday life, furnish social scientists with a diverse array of topics that demand urgent engagement. New biomedical technologies repeatedly create the possibility, not merelyof new knowledge, but also of new forms of knowledge, and new social formations too. The latter form the subject-matter of the companion volume to this one (New Genetics, New Social Formations, Routledge, 2006). They in turn create the possibility of new bases for social identity, individual and collective. The contributions brought together in this volume report empirical research exploring a number of complementary aspects of genetics and the formation of identities. Identifying the relevance of innovation in biomedical science for self-identity is not in itself a new observation. Recent sociological, anthropological and historical studies of medical or scientific systems, institutions and practices have repeatedly emphasised the intersection of technology, knowledge and identity. The work of Foucault is among the key sources of inspiration here, as is the work of the author who inspired him, Canguilhem. Indeed, Foucault himself mapped out a programme of research on the cultural history of genetic knowledge. In 1969, in his candidacy presentation at the Colle`ge de France (Foucault 1991), he outlined (as he was required to do) a plan for the classes he would deliver. He identified as the central topic ‘the knowledge of heredity’. He delineated a programme of work on nineteenthcentury thought: ‘. . . starting from breeding techniques, on through attempts to improve species, experiments with intensive cultivation, efforts to combat animal and plant epidemics, and culminating in the establishment of a genetics whose birth date can be placed at the beginning of the twentieth century.’ While Foucault’s own programme remained unrealised in that form, some forty years or so later we find an increasing number ofsocial scientists working on the profound implications of new regimes of genetic knowledge. The emergence of modern medicine, Foucault had previously argued,was shaped by key changes in technology closely coupled with changes in the institutional context that created a qualitative transformation in medical perception in early nineteenth-century France, a transformation that in turn sets the course for modern biomedical knowledge more generally (Foucault 1972). Canguilhem (1978) also argued that, within the system of knowledge that underpins modern medicine, the ‘normal’ and the ‘pathological’ represent two quite distinct frames of reference. One cannot read the pathological off by just extending the range of physiological values beyond the normal limits. Pathology is not merely a quantitative deviation from the norm, but a qualitatively distinct state. David Armstrong, among others, has extended these ideas, suggesting that in the development of twentieth-century medicine we can identify further organising principles that extend the classical, modern notion of ‘the clinic’ (Armstrong 1983). He identifies, for instance, the mode of knowledge characteristic of ‘the dispensary’ that takes the medical gaze outwards into the community, that identifies rates and values of normal and unhealthy states. This a medicine, not of individual bodies, but of populations and communities, members of which are susceptible to classification and enumeration. Such a mode of medical understanding puts in question Canguilhem’s radical distinction between the normal and the pathological as a universal one, rather than a context-specific characteristic of the classically ‘modern’ clinic. In more recent years, we have had added to the armamentarium of biomedical knowledge various forms of ‘risk’ assessment, in which distinctions between the normal and the pathological are transformed once more. The identification of genetic risks or susceptibilities for inherited medical conditions can have far-reaching implications for personal and collective identity. This intellectual programme has been advanced by a number of authorswho discuss the implications of the new medical technologies and their consequences. Rose (2001), for instance, has provided several key discussions of the new politics of ‘life itself’, developing ideas on ‘biovalue’ from Waldby (2000), among others. This perspective is also developed in the chapter by Venkatesan in this volume (Chapter 11), in which she reviews contemporary perspectives on biomedical innovation from a Foucauldian perspective. The scientific and professional identification of risk can create newsources of personal identity and self-perception (cf. Novas and Rose 2000). Risk has the potential to transform the relatively stable categories of normality and pathology. The individual biography and the medical history are given a particular salience, in that future physical and mental wellbeing may be perceived as determined, or at least heavily circumscribed, by genetic fate. We now know a very great deal about the personal and interpersonal implications of major genetic conditions, such as Huntington’sDisease, breast and colorectal cancer, various forms of muscular dystrophy (myotonic, Duchenne, Becker), haemochromatosis and cystic fibrosis. We know that contemporary biomedical research is identifying ever more medical conditions that have at least a genetic component. Physical conditions are now being complemented by psychological conditions in which genetic bases are becoming incriminated: schizophrenia, bipolar disorder, attention deficit disorder and severe depression are all being linked to susceptibility genes. While genetic and environmental interactions are bound to be complex, and further research is certain to result in yet more complexity, the extension of genetic medicine into psychological conditions and behavioural traits will lead to yet further claims for genetic predestination in many domains of everyday life. Genetic susceptibility may not predict actual onset with any certainty, and may not be able to foretell the severity of the condition, but it has the potential to transform our sense of ourselves as embodied social actors, our sense of biographical development, and our sense of personal stability. There is no doubt that recent developments in genetic science havehelped to transform biomedical science and wider medical practice. It would be unwise, however, to attribute all such change exclusively to the scientific revolution occasioned by the human genome project and the exponential growth in post-genomic research. While genomic science has been a significant motor in the development of medical thought, we must not forget that many key idioms of embodiment, health, illness and identity pre-date the genomic revolution itself. Notions of risk clearly pre-date the identification of many illnesses with genetic predispositions – although it is incontrovertible that genetic medicine has given risk a renewed urgency and currency. Likewise, we have not had to wait until the Human Genome Project and its associated activities for the idiom of inheritance to capture inter-generational physical similarities, nor indeed for the observation of familial medical conditions. Genetic medicine sharpens the collective awareness of these phenomena, and has an important impact on medical thought. But it is not a uniquely transformative set of events. It is clear that genetic medicine can contribute to a generic array of risks, susceptibilities and biological bases that impinge on identity, but it is not unique. It is clear that we must avoid genetic exceptionalism. An increasing emphasis on biological predisposition gives rise to issuesof determinism and the theodicy of suffering. A genetic basis for ill-health can imply a deterministic or fatalistic attitude towards suffering. Inherited, genetic conditions appear to be a biological form of destiny, an implacably shaping influence on the unfolding of one’s life. Inherited predispositions for major conditions such as Huntington’s disease can ultimately determine one’s personal fate. Likewise, such fate can be transmitted to one’s children. Familial conditions and risks can be detected through genetic testing, if suspected. Spontaneous mutations can also give rise to genetic conditions – but are not familial, and are unpredictable. They can, nevertheless, beinexorable in their effects on offspring. The theodicy of genetic illness directs attention towards the search for explanation and meaning. The parents and other family members of affected children can search their own and others’ biographies for explanations. Family trees are inspected by family members as much as they are by genetic specialists. Family members engage in mutual surveillance in the attempt to identify the locus of a genetic trait within a kindred, and its mode of transmission (Featherstone et al. 2006). There is ample scope for the attribution of blame. Likewise, self-blame and feelings of spoiled identity (stigma) can pervade the everyday world of families with genetic conditions. Family members can therefore seek to interpolate personal and biographical reasons for inherited medical conditions. Genetic risk runs counter to most contemporary discourse concerning personal responsibility and health. We are exhorted to reduce our exposure to health risks, such as poor diet, tobacco or alcohol intake. Environmental factors over which individuals exercise little or no control – such as pollution and industrial hazards – are increasingly brought within a discourse of respon
DOI:10.4324/9780203962923-8