What Does That Mean? Complementizers and Epistemic Authority

A core goal of research in language is to understand the factors that guide choice of linguistic form where more than one option is syntactically well-formed. We discuss one case of optionality that has generated longstanding discussion: the choice of either using or dropping the English complementi...

Full description

Saved in:
Bibliographic Details
Published inOpen mind (Cambridge, Mass.) Vol. 8; pp. 366 - 394
Main Authors Tollan, Rebecca, Palaz, Bilge
Format Journal Article
LanguageEnglish
Published One Broadway, 12th Floor, Cambridge, Massachusetts 02142, USA MIT Press 26.03.2024
The MIT Press
Subjects
Online AccessGet full text
ISSN2470-2986
2470-2986
DOI10.1162/opmi_a_00135

Cover

Loading…
More Information
Summary:A core goal of research in language is to understand the factors that guide choice of linguistic form where more than one option is syntactically well-formed. We discuss one case of optionality that has generated longstanding discussion: the choice of either using or dropping the English complementizer in sentences like . Existing psycholinguistic analyses tie -usage to production pressures associated with sentence planning (Ferreira & Dell, ), avoidance of ambiguity (Hawkins, ), and relative information density (Jaeger, ). Building on observations from cross-linguistic fieldwork, we present a novel proposal in which English can serve to mark a speaker’s “epistemic authority” over the information packaged within the embedded clause; that is, it indicates that the speaker has more knowledge of the embedded proposition compared with their addressee and thus has a perspective that they believe their addressee doesn’t share. Testing this proposal with a forced-choice task and a series of corpus surveys, we find that English is keyed to the use of embedded speaker (first-person) subject pronouns and occurs in sentences containing newsworthy information. Our account of -optionality takes into account why is associated with both (i) a dense information signal and (ii) semantic-pragmatic content, as well as extending to cases of non-optionality in subject/sentence-initial clauses (e.g., * ) and fragment answers (e.g., * ), where is required.
Bibliography:2024
ObjectType-Article-1
SourceType-Scholarly Journals-1
ObjectType-Feature-2
content type line 23
Competing Interests: The authors declare no conflict of interests.
ISSN:2470-2986
2470-2986
DOI:10.1162/opmi_a_00135